Feb 5, 2013

Richard Rorty, the Pope: truth, ethics and relativisms

Pragmatist philosopher Richard Rorty gave one of his last public presentations in a 2005 lecture in Italy called “An ethics for today: finding common ground for philosophy and religion.” In his lecture Rorty contrasts his own view with that of the Catholic Church and clarifies his own understanding of relativism.

Rorty describes the Church as affirming the reality of a “structure of human existence, which can serve as a moral reference point.” For his part, Rorty sides with John Stuart Mill in holding that the only moral obligation humans have is that of “helping one another satisfy our desires, thus achieving the greatest possible amount of happiness.”[1] This clearly utilitarian ethic is one for which Rorty makes no apology. In the face of the Church’s view that utilitarianism makes animals of human beings, Rorty claims, in revealing phraseology, that on the contrary, “utilitarianism exalts us by offering us a challenging moral ideal. Utilitarianism leads to heroic and self-sacrificing efforts on behalf of social justice.”[2]

One must assume that the irony of his positive moral appraisal of heroism, self-sacrifice and social justice is not lost on Rorty who describes himself as a liberal ironist. But irrespective of whether Rorty acknowledges the strange juxtaposition of utilitarianism and moral virtues such as heroism, there is a clear appeal to moral values above and beyond, or at least additional to, that of increasing the net amount of happiness on the planet. While social justice might conceivably be defined in utilitarian terms as maximising human happiness or desire satisfaction, that is not the case with heroism and self-sacrifice. As normally understood, and when not distorted to fit a utilitarian scheme, one can imagine classic situations of heroism or self-sacrifice that neither increase net happiness nor were even intended to do so.


Although an appeal to the exaltation, heroism and self-sacrifice of human beings is to use non-utilitarian, morally loaded terms, Rorty assures us that “such [heroic and self-sacrificing] efforts are entirely compatible with the claim that there is no such thing as the structure of human existence.”[3] With George Santayana, Rorty believes that the only source of moral ideals is the human imagination and he rejects the superstitious view that moral ideals are grounded in any structure of human existence.[4] He says:

To give oneself over to a moral ideal is like giving oneself over to another human being. When we fall in love with another person, we do not ask about the source or the nature of our obligation to cherish that person’s welfare. It is equally pointless to do so when we have fallen in love with an ideal. Most of Western philosophy is, like Christian theology, an attempt to get in touch with something larger than ourselves. So to accept Santayana’s view, as I do, is to repudiate the tradition that Heidegger called onto-theology. That repudiation means ceasing to ask both metaphysical questions about the ground or the source of our ideals and epistemological questions about how one can be certain that one has chosen the correct ideal. 9

This passage, which unnecessarily forces a wedge between the repudiation of onto-theology and the possibility of any sort of metaphysical questioning, is one I will return to after finishing this exposition of Rorty’s paper. Suffice to say that with respect to epistemology, of course one cannot “be certain that one has chosen the correct ideal,” but the question is whether Rorty’s repudiation of such questions is because of that epistemic uncertainty or because he wants to make an ontological claim about the non-existence of such ideals as part of the structure of human existence. If it is the second, as seems clear in this paper, then it also involves an implicit epistemic claim to know that there is no source of such ideals beyond the human imagination. One need not abandon the quest for truth because one recognises that certainty is a chimera, let alone, as Rorty does, to make a truth claim about such ideals not existing while at the same time repudiating the asking of such questions. The situation sounds suspiciously like the sort of family argument stopper that goes, “I’m just going to say this and then I’m leaving the room and not going to argue any more,” which leaves the interlocutor frustrated at having been presented with a poor argument without recourse to further discussion.

Rorty elaborates on his metaphor of falling in love by saying that there is no possibility of an appeal to neutral criteria to choose between two people or between two ideals such as atheistic and religious forms of spirituality. So in the face of the demands of the onto-theological tradition which insists on raising metaphysical and epistemological questions, Rorty says that conversion cannot be rationally justified: “It is futile to look for a demonstration that one has turned in the right direction.”[5]

Rorty makes it clear where the differences lie between himself and the onto-theological tradition—and more generally, speculative philosophy—as he advocates a sort of atheistic but spiritual relativism. Responding to a homily by the then Cardinal Ratzinger, which speaks of “a dictatorship of relativism that does not recognise anything as definitive,” Rorty dons the relativist mantle willingly—something he has resisted vehemently in past writings—and in the process, he clarifies the nature of his relativism. But it is founded on a non-relativist dogma that there is no structure of human existence in which ideals are founded and which therefore leaves ideals as relative because they serve the purpose of increasing human happiness. Aligning himself with philosophers such as Santayana and John Stuart Mill, he says,

[They] do indeed refuse to recognize anything as definitive. This is because they think that every reported object of philosophical speculation or of religious worship is a product of the human imagination. Someday it may be replaced by a better object. There is no destined end to this process of replacement, no point at which we can claim to have found the correct ideal once and for all. There is nothing already in existence to which our moral convictions should try to correspond.[6]

So rather than being “carried about by every wind of doctrine” as the now-current Pope describes relativists, Rorty takes the moral high ground describing philosophers like himself as open to new ideas, willing to “consider all suggestions about what might increase human happiness” and claiming that this doctrinal openness “is the only way to avoid the evils of the past.”[7]

Rorty clarifies his atypical use of the terms ‘fundamentalism’ and ‘relativism’ that allows him to refer to the Pope as fundamentalist and himself as relativist; fundamentalism is the view that “ideals are valid only when grounded in reality” as opposed to the more typical understanding that sees fundamentalism as a naive invocation of scripture. Adopting this meaning allows Rorty to define relativism as the denial of fundamentalism; at a minimum presumably, ideals can be valid even if not grounded in reality. However Rorty goes further: “Relativists on this definition are those who believe that we would be better off without such notions as unconditional moral obligations grounded in the structure of human existence.”[8] But this explicit definition of relativism introduces a value judgment not found in the denial of fundamentalism as a belief that ideals are grounded in reality. Does this matter? Only that Rorty’s explicit definition doesn’t actually tackle the question of whether ideals are or are not grounded in reality; it only says we would be better off without that notion. Is this because the notion is wrong or simply unpragmatic? This brings us again to the heart of the question of Rorty’s view on truth. Does he think his liberal ironic pragmatism is the way forward because he really does regard truth (with respect to ideals in the current discussion) as nonsensical, or is truth for Rorty simply unattainable? Or perhaps he believes that because the latter is true (!) then so is the first?

Rorty quotes Ratzinger and says that Mill, Dewey, Habermas (and by implication Rorty himself) share the cardinal’s view of relativism:

The cardinal summarized the relativists’ line of argument as follows: “Democracy is said to be founded on no one’s being able to claim to know the right way forward. It draws life from all the ways acknowledging each other as fragmentary attempts at improvement and trying to agree in common through dialogue. A free society is said to be a relativistic society. Only on this condition can it remain free and open-ended.”[9]

Further expounding his own view, Rorty says that the three philosophers he mentions share in a view of truth as “what wins out in the marketplace of ideas rather than correspondence to an antecedent reality” and that they see democracy as essentially relativist in Rorty’s sense because it is based on the “idea that nothing is sacred because everything is up for discussion.”[10]

While Ratzinger acknowledges the validity of some relativity in the realms of politics and society, such relativity is not unlimited and when politics tries to be redemptive, he says, it has usurped the work of God. Rorty agrees that politics should not try to be redemptive, but not because redemption is God’s business; rather because “redemption was a bad idea in the first place. Human beings need to be made happier, but they do not need to be redeemed.”[11] Humans according to Rorty are not “degraded beings, not immaterial souls imprisoned in material bodies, not innocent souls corrupted by original sin.” Rather they are Nietzsche’s ‘clever animals’ that have grown through history to be cooperative, to be “brave, imaginative, idealistic, self-improving.”[12]

So, rejecting Ratzinger’s Platonic spirituality, which is rooted in the infinite and the possibility of immortality, Rorty affirms a secular spirituality consisting of “an exalted sense of new possibilities opening up for finite beings.” The difference between these two views is that between “the hope to transcend the finite and the hope for a world in which human beings live far happier lives than they live at the present time.”[13] And, he says, “though largely Christian in its original inspiration, the political idealism of modern times has no need or use for the idea that there is something over and above what Cardinal Ratzinger called ‘the ego and its desires.’”[14]

Rorty’s utilitarianism is clear; for him, no desires are bad in themselves although some do obstruct the overall satisfaction of desire: “there is no such thing as intrinsically evil desire.”[15] Rorty describes Peter Singer’s idea of “enlarging the circle of the ‘we’” as a case where relativism leads to beneficial change; he cites three examples: when poverty and wealth are seen as mutable rather than immutable social institutions then the rich see the poor as fellow citizens rather than ordained by God to their station in life. Similarly, he says, the success of feminism and the growing heterosexual understanding of homosexuals are examples where a Rortian relativism has provoked a change for the better.

However, Rorty does not make his point; there is no reason to assume that ‘enlarging the circle of the “we”’ cannot occur based on an enlarged or changed understanding of what norms are immutable. That is, while Rorty claims that it is the movement in thinking from fundamentalism (as he defines it) to relativism that leads to the benefits he cites, others—Christians included—might say that a better understanding of, or a revision of what counts as immutable norms, lies at the heart of social changes for the better. Christians would say that despite a belief that slavery or the inequality of the sexes are rooted in an immutable order, the Church was wrong. And not only that, but the very reason that those past positions can be criticised is on the basis of new understandings based on the immutability of the equal dignity of all human beings. We will return to discuss further Rorty’s relativism and the question of immutable norms.

Rorty finishes his paper complicating an already unclear discussion. He raises the question of how to decide between the Jamesian view that “any desire has a right to be fulfilled if it does not interfere with the fulfilment of other desires” and the view of those who see “certain desires and acts as intrinsically evil.”[16] Such a decision cannot be made, he says, on the basis of philosophical reflection—which, rather than constraining the imagination, is in fact one of the products of the human imagination. Nor can a choice be made on any particular reading of history, which would be simply one among many readings.

The answer is that “our choice between alternative principles is determined by our preferences between possible futures for humanity.”[17] Neither the reasoning of philosophy nor the experience of history offer a neutral court of appeal and so, for relativists like Rorty, the struggle is between “two great products of the human imagination;” the pope’s view appeals to a truth greater than humanity while the relativist’s vision holds that “there never was, and never will be, a truth that is greater than we are. The very idea of such a truth is a confusion of ideals with power.”[18]

What are we to make of Rorty’s defence of relativism over fundamentalism as he has defined them? Rorty’s disarming turn of phrase makes the lack of rigour less transparent but before criticising him for a lack of philosophical rigour, his own words against the possibility of resolving such matters through philosophical reflection need to be remembered. Hasn’t he closed the possibility of criticism with his appeal to preferences rather than philosophy? By his own parameters, his writing need not claim to be rigorous because it is just one product of the human imagination.

 This sort of defence simply won’t work and despite his clear statements, I doubt that Rorty would explicitly appeal to it. He falls into reflexive incomprehensibility if he simply sloughs off the tradition of serious argument as long as he is trying to say something true—in fact, as long as he is trying to say anything at all. Whatever he says, he comes under critical judgement to see if his communication points to truth or not; Is this the way things are? is the question we ask as we read his work which purports in its own self-deprecating way to be telling us about the way things are.

All references are from Rorty, Richard, Elijah Dann, and Gianni Vattimo. An Ethics for Today: Finding Common Ground between Philosophy and Religion.  New York: Columbia University Press, 2011.


[1] 8

[2] 8

[3] 8

[4] 8

[5] 10

[6] 10

[7] 10-11

[8] 11

[9] 11

[10] 12

[11] 13

[12] 13

[13] 14

[14] 15

[15] 15

[16] 16

[17] 16


[18] 17

0 comments:

Post a Comment